Monday, 19 December 2016

Legal Realism; Over-dependence on the Judge’s Discretion? Jurisprudence

By Miriam Maina LLB
Abstract.
The objective of this essay is to assess the Realist school of thought and its dependence on the judge as the ultimate law maker, based on particularly the contributions made by Justice Benjamin Cardozo. More importantly, it seeks to elaborate to what extent it agrees with the theories advanced by the said jurist, and what different prepositions can be put forward, and the authorities informing these differing opinions. Finally, it will look into the inconsistencies that water down the probative value in other jurisprudential schools of thought, and distinctly, the positivist approach taken by Hans Kelsen. The objectives stated above will be tackled in two sections, where the first will develop the realist school of thought exclusively, and the second will look into Kelsen’s approach and the inconsistencies thereto.
Introduction
The realist school of thought advances the idea that the law is not codified rules, directives and principles. [1]The law here is the prophesies of what the court will do in fact[2], i.e. the behavior of the judiciary. Subsequently, this school does not analyze legislation as done in other schools such as the positivist school, but lays emphasis on the judge as the law maker.
Section I: Justice Benjamin Cardozo’s contribution to Realism, and to what extent this paper agrees with these contributions
Like other realists, Justice Cardozo advanced the view that the law did not only comprise of determinate rules, but rather it was highly contingent upon extraneous influences of the particular judge. According to him, the judicial processes that interpreted the law are not supposed to stand in isolation, but should be alive to social realities. In fact, these social realities ought to be central to the art of judicial adjudication. This position develops both the realist and sociological schools of thought. Justice Cardozo also favors the approach that every judicial system should not only reflect the nature of the present society, but also that of the judge. He argues that the judge’s sympathies, conscious and unconscious should be taken into account when analyzing a court process. This input is invaluable to the realist school, but a differing opinion is inevitable especially regarding the extent to which factors such as the sympathies of the judge should reflect in a judicial process.
It is a widely recognized fact that an impartial ruling should be based on no other factor other than the law and the facts of the particular circumstance. Nonetheless, judges are given an extent of discretion to apply the law liberally in order to enable them arrive at the best answers for the legal questions at hand. The predicament that arises then from Cardozo’s work is, at what point and to what extent should these sympathies affect a judicial finding? Should a judge’s ruling be hinged upon his political, social, and/or economic preferences or affiliations? In solving this dilemma, issues of consideration should be the peculiarities and uniqueness of each situation that is brought for adjudication before the courts. In that regard, the law should be applied with the intent of providing the best available answer for the present legal questions.
This paper concedes to the fact that the “right answer” to every scenario is not written down in any particular legislation or scholarly works, and hence the need for discretion and limited deviation from the realm of the law to other considerations. However, it is vital that this deviation is controlled. It is hereby argued that Ronald Dworkin put forward the most befitting antidote to this complexity. In progressing his “Right answer” theory, he cautions that there exists a right answer to every legal problem, and this answer is informed by reason, and requirements of fairness and justice as dimensions of morality. This yardstick considerably limits the said discretion, and in the alternative lays down the preconditions to govern discretion.
Section II; Inconsistencies in Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law.
Hans Kelsen, a positivist, put forward his pure theory of Law, arguing that the law ought to be eliminated from everything that is strictly not law; its aim is to free the science of law from alien elements[3]. This “alien elements” could include politics, economics, morality, justice etc. This theory has the effect of placing the law in a vacuum, where it should supposedly regulate and govern society, without getting acquainted with societal attributes and qualities. In other words, society should dance to the law’s tune, instead of the other way round. But weren’t social and societal interactions the reason why the law arose? And as such, the law should fit into society and not society fitting into the law. Put differently, separating the law from the inherent characteristics of society makes it rigid and blind adherence to such law has the inevitable consequence of injustices.
Basing this argument on the realist approach developed earlier, it is the role of the judge therefore to determine when to apply the law in it pure form i.e. without consideration of “foreign” factors, and when to be liberal and allow influences of justice and morality to reflect in his judicial conclusions.
Conclusion.
A judge’s discretion has to be guided by certain considerations, for instance justice and reason, especially when the law and facts at hand are uncertain. This is to ensure that the results of judicial processes yield solutions to the legal questions that arise.


[1] Key Issues On Jurisprudence- Omony John Paul.
[2] Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes.
[3] Pure theory of law-Hans Kelsen.

No comments:

Post a Comment